Education and Disciple
Bertrand Russell
Any serious educational theory must
consist of two parts: a conception of the ends of life, and a science of psychological
dynamics, i.e. of the laws of mental change. Two men who differ as to the ends
of life cannot hope to agree about education. The educational machine, throughout
Western civilization, is dominated by two ethical theories: that of Christianity,
and that of nationalism. These two, when taken seriously, are incompatible,
as is becoming evident in Germany. For my part, I hold that, where they differ,
Christianity is preferable, but where they agree, both are mistaken. The conception
which I should substitute as the purpose of education is civilization, a term
which, as I mean it, has a definition which is partly individual, partly social.
It consists, in the individual, of both intellectual and moral qualities: intellectually,
a certain minimum of general knowledge, technical skill in one's own profession,
and a habit of forming opinions on evidence; morally, of impartiality, kindliness,
and a modicum of self-control. I should add a quality which is neither moral
nor intellectual, but perhaps physiological: zest and joy of life. In communities,
civilization demands respect for law, justice as between man and man, purposes
not involving permanent injury to any section of the human race, and intelligent
adaptation of means to ends. If these are to be the purpose of education, it
is a question for the science of psychology to consider what can be done towards
realizing them, and, in particular, what degree of freedom is likely to prove
most effective.
On the question of freedom in education
there are at present three main schools of thought, deriving partly from differences
as to ends and partly from differences in psychological theory. There are those
who say that children should be completely free, however
bad they may be; there are those who say they should be completely subject to
authority, however good they may be; and there are those who say they should
be free, but in spite of freedom they should be always good. This last party
is larger than it has any logical right to be; children, like adults, will not
all be virtuous if they are all free. The belief that liberty will ensure moral
perfection is a relic of Rousseauism, and would not survive a study of animals
and babies. Those who hold this belief think that education should have no positive
purpose, but should merely offer an environment suitable for spontaneous development.
I cannot agree with this school, which seems to me too individualistic, and
unduly indifferent to the importance of knowledge. We live in communities which
require co-operation, and it would be utopian to expect all the necessary co-operation
to result from spontaneous impulse. The existence of a large population on a
limited area is only possible owing to science and technique; education must,
therefore, hand on the necessary minimum of these. The educators who allow most
freedom are men whose success depends upon a degree of benevolence, self-control,
and trained intelligence which can hardly be generated where every impulse is
left unchecked; their merits, therefore, are not likely to be perpetuated if
their methods are undiluted. Education, viewed from a social standpoint, must
be something more positive than a mere opportunity for growth. It must, of course,
provide this, but it must also provide a mental and moral equipment which children
cannot acquire entirely for themselves.
The arguments in favour of a great degree
of freedom in education are derived not from man's natural goodness, but from
the effects of authority, both on those who suffer it and on those who exercise
it. Those who are subject to authority become either submissive or rebellious,
and each attitude has its drawbacks.
The submissive lose initiative, both in
thought and action; moreover, the anger generated by the feeling of being thwarted
tends to find an outlet in bullying those who are weaker. That is why tyrannical
institutions are self-perpetuating: what a man has suffered from his father
he inflicts upon his son, and the humiliations which he remembers having endured
at his public school he passes on to Ònatives" when he becomes an empire-builder.
Thus an unduly authoritative education turns the pupils into timid tyrants,
incapable of either claiming or tolerating originality in word or deed. The
effect upon the educators is even worse: they tend to become sadistic disciplinarians,
glad to inspire terror, and content to inspire nothing else. As these men represent
knowledge, the pupils acquire a horror of knowledge, which, among the English
upper-class, is supposed to be part of human nature, but is really part of the
well-grounded hatred of the authoritarian pedagogue.
Rebels, on the other hand,, though they
may be necessary, can hardly be just to what exists. Moreover, there are many
ways of rebelling, and only a small minority of these are wise. Galileo was
a rebel and was wise; believers in the flat-earth theory are equally rebels,
but are foolish. There is a great danger in the tendency to suppose that opposition
to authority is essentially meritorious and that unconventional opinions are
bound to be correct: no useful purpose is served by smashing lamp-posts or maintaining
Shakespeare to be no poet. Yet this excessive rebelliousness is often the effect
that too much authority has on spirited pupils. And when rebels become educators,
they sometimes encourage defiance in their pupils, for whom at the same time
they are trying to produce a perfect environment, although these two aims are
scarcely compatible.
What is wanted is neither submissiveness
nor rebellion, but good nature, and general friendliness both to people and
to new ideas. These qualities are due in part to physical causes, to which old-fashioned
educators paid too little attention; but they are due still more to freedom
from the feeling of baffled impotence which arises when vital impulses are thwarted.
If the young are to grow into friendly adults, it is necessary, in most cases,
that they should feel their environment friendly. This requires that there should
be a certain sympathy with the child's important desires, and not merely an
attempt to use him for some abstract end such as the glory of God or the greatness
of one's country. And, in teaching, every attempt should be made to cause the
pupil to feel that it is worth his while to know what is being taught-at least
when this is true. When the pupil co-operates willingly, he learns twice as
fast and with half the fatigue. All these are valid reasons for a very great
degree of freedom.
It is easy, however, to carry the argument
too far. It is not desirable that children, in avoiding the vices of the slave,
should acquire those of the aristocrat. Consideration for others, not only in
great matters, but also in little everyday things, is an essential element in
civilization, without which social life would be intolerable. I am not thinking
of mere forms of politeness, such as saying "please" and "thank you": formal
manners are most fully developed among barbarians, and diminish with every advance
in culture. I am thinking rather of willingness to take a fair share of necessary
work, to be obliging in small ways that save trouble on the balance. Sanity
itself is a form of politeness and it is not desirable to give a child a sense
of omnipotence, or a belief that adults exist only to minister to the pleasures
of the young. And those who disapprove of the existence of the idle rich are
hardly consistent if they bring up their children without any sense that work
is necessary, and without the habits that make continuous application possible.
There is another consideration to which
some advocates of freedom attach too little importance. In a community of children
which is left without adult interference there is a tyranny of the stronger,
which is likely to be far more brutal than most adult tyranny. If two children
of two or three years old are left to play together, they will, after a few
fights, discover which is bound to be the victor, and the other will then become
a slave. Where the number of children is larger, one or two acquire complete
mastery, and the others have far less liberty than they would have if the adults
interfered to protect the weaker and less pugnacious. Consideration for others
does not, with most children, arise spontaneously, but has to be taught, and
can hardly be taught except by the exercise of authority. This is perhaps the
most important argument against the abdication of the adults.
I do not think that educators have yet
solved the problem of combining the desirable forms of freedom with the necessary
minimum of moral training. The right solution, it must be admitted, is often
made impossible by parents before the child is brought to an enlightened school.
just as psychoanalysts, from their clinical experience, conclude that we are
all mad, so the authorities in modern schools, from their contact with pupils
whose parents have made them unmanageable, are disposed to conclude that all
children are "difficult" and all parents utterly foolish. Children who have
been driven wild by parental tyranny (which often takes the form of solicitous
affection) may require a longer or shorter period of complete liberty before
they can view any adult without suspicion. But children who have been sensibly
handled at home can bear to be checked in minor ways, so long as they feel that
they are being helped in the ways that they themselves regard as important.
Adults who like children, and are not reduced to a condition of nervous exhaustion
by their company, can achieve a great deal in the way of discipline without
ceasing to be regarded with friendly feelings by their pupils.
I think modern educational theorists are
inclined to attach too much importance to the negative virtue of not interfering
with children, and too little to the positive merit of enjoying their company.
If you have the sort of liking for children that many people have for horses
or dogs, they will be apt to respond to your suggestions, and to accept prohibitions,
perhaps with some good-humoured grumbling, but without resentment. It is no
use to have the sort of liking that consists in regarding them as a field for
valuable social endeavour, orÑwhat amounts to the same thingÑas an outlet for
power-impulses. No child will be grateful for an interest in him that springs
from the thought that he will have a vote to be secured for your party or a
body to be sacrificed to king and country. The desirable sort of interest is
that which consists in spontaneous pleasure in the presence of children, without
any ulterior purpose. Teachers who have this quality will seldom need to interfere
with children's freedom, but will be able to do so, when necessary, without
causing psychological damage.
Unfortunately, it is utterly impossible
for over-worked teachers to preserve an instinctive liking for children; they
are bound to come to feel towards them as the proverbial confectioner's apprentice
does towards macaroons. I do not think that education ought to be anyone's whole
profession: it should be undertaken for at most two hours a day by people whose
remaining hours are spent away from children. The society of the young is fatiguing,
especially when strict discipline is avoided. Fatigue, in the end, produces
irritation, which is likely to express itself somehow, whatever theories the
harassed teacher may have taught himself or herself to believe. The necessary
friendliness cannot be preserved by self-control alone. But where it exists,
it should be unnecessary to have rules in advance as to how "naughty" children
are to be treated, since impulse is likely to lead to the right decision, and
almost any decision will be right if the child feels that you like him. No rules,
however wise, are a substitute for affection and tact.
On
Denoting (1905)
Vagueness (1923)
Icarus
or The Future of Science (1924)
What is an Agnostic
Knowledge and
Wisdom
Why I am
not a Christian (06.03.1927)
In
Praise of Idleness (1932)
Of Co-Operation
(18.05.1932)
On Sales Resistance
(22.06.1932)
On Modern
Uncertainty (20.07.1932)
What is the Soul?
(28.09.1932)
On youthful
Cynism (1930)
Philosophical
Consequences of Relativity (1626)
On Astrologers
How
to become a Man of Genius
Education
and Disciple
What
Desires are politically important? (Speech at the Nobel Award, 11.12.1950)
Prolog to his Autobiography: What
I have lived for